Book review (2009): The Terrorist in Search of Humanity: Militant Islam & Global Politics
Review of The Terrorist in Search of Humanity:
Militant Islam and Global Politics
by Faisal Devji; New
Delhi, 2008
Reviewed by Dilip Simeon; for Biblio, Jan-Feb 2009
NB: The title of the review ('The Sinner and the Saint'), as it appears in Biblio, was editorially given, and not my choice.
This essay in the history of ideas traces the
trajectory of Islamic militancy and its implications for modern politics,
including the so‑called global war on terror, nicknamed GWOT by the author.
Written from a South Asian perspective, it is a healthy antidote to the
instrumentalist discourse that addresses the issue from the standpoint of
Western security. It is also a critique of modernity and the self‑deceptions of
the international order: “liberalism has no presence outside the nation‑state,
which is why the international order these states operate in has never been
liberal”. Devji alerts us to the arrival of a globalised and mediatised
phenomenon that may not be explained away. He notes that networks have infiltrated
hierarchies as the form of political activity, and that bin Laden and his
followers have dispensed not only with parties, but also with armies and
battlefields. They have even ceased to pose a military challenge. And yet “the
United States can no longer wage war, it can only mount enormously costly and
destructive spectacles of deterrence or revenge”. The upshot is that war has
been de‑militarised and made a police
operation, civil and military law have begun to overlap, categories of
prisoners have been reduced to the status of slaves and Western political
institutions severely compromised.
The Terrorist in Search of Humanity takes us back to the non-cooperation movement in the
aftermath of the Great War, and reminds us (with reference to the Khilafat
agitation) that Mahatma Gandhi was “the most creative modern thinker of the
caliphate: a Hindu who received the adulation of Muslim divines”. Not to mention his principled opposition to
the Zionist idea in 1921, as Britain and France carved up the remains of the
Ottaman Empire. Maulana Azad, Iqbal and Abul Ala Mawdudi all make an
appearance, and their ideas seriously considered. Yet the argument that
Gandhi’s non-cooperation was a “negative practice”, a “suprapolitical”
manifestation of worldly withdrawal, that he sought the collapse of an evil
politics without proposing an alternative, is unconvincing, as is his citation
of these factors as disclosing a similarity between Gandhi and today’s
militants. Devji observes that the militants’ practice of disclaiming of
responsibility for their violence “possesses a profoundly negative core”; yet
later in the book he tells us they have revolutionised Islam and offered us a
vision of the future.
Devji’s observations on law are an insightful
commentary on the de-legitimisation and fragmentation of the international
legal order. He points out that arguments about humanity take precedence in
radical Islamic rhetoric. Muslims are less a religious group and more the
contemporary representatives of human suffering. Whereas imperialists cite
humanitarian ideals in pursuit of their objectives, both NGOs and militants accuse the West of
hypocrisy in its promotion of human rights. Indeed, declassified interrogations
and public statements show that hypocrisy is an obsession in militant rhetoric.
The USA, UK and their allies have flouted international law and covenants, and
even their own laws. The author points to the pre‑modern juridical custom of
judging religious communities by their own laws and practices - a pluralism
often invoked by militants under trial. Given the absence of a global politics
says Devji, pluralism serves to “assign responsibility according to the
divergent principles of multiple actors, which is why hypocrisy becomes such a
foundational category for it”. This illustrates "how intimately terrorist
practices are linked with those of their enemies, whose interventions also
invariably kill some civilians in the name of protecting others...it might well
be that this intimacy between the terrorist and the humanitarian is what lends
militant Islam its popularity”. He examines the Guantanamo statement of Khalid
Sheikh Mohammad, “the 9/11 linchpin”, who adopted "the Gandhian practice
of pleading guilty before a court he considered illegitimate, thus turning his
hearing into one for the tribunal itself”. Militant pluralism has torn Islamic
law “from its traditional moorings to become the source for a thoroughly
individualized jurisprudence whose first and only rule is being true to
oneself”. Terrorism has adopted the language of swaraj, or self-rule.
Thus a global society has come into being, but lacks
political institutions adequate to its name. Islamic militancy represents the
search for a global politics in an ambience where universally available images and
information are consumed in individualised isolation. For environmentalists,
pacifists and holy warriors alike, “global humanity has...replaced an
international proletariat as the Sleeping Beauty of history”. I would make the
caveat that the international proletariat was never the Sleeping Beauty, but
the universal representative of human suffering ‑ much as today's radical
clerics portray the Ummah. And the idealised representative of universal
humanity always requires an intermediary between itself and its oppressor, a
Platonic tyrant to command its activity. It is precisely the violence embodied
in the claim (whether made by an individual or a group) to represent an entire
community, class, or nation that marks this militancy as yet another contingent
of modernity's loyal opposition. But that is another debate.
The book educates us with its intimate details about
the world of Muslim radicalism. The central role of the media in the strategies
of the militants underlines the global aspect of the phenomenon, and
strengthens Devji's argument about their need to converse with an abstract
humanity. The motivations of the London bombers of 2005 derived not from
personal experience, but the televised suffering of Muslims in other parts of
the world. We learn of the website "Al Ansar's Top 20" from Iraq,
where insurgents send in clips of attacks that are ranked as in a music
countdown. The pre‑recorded video‑tapes of suicide bombers convey to a global
audience the discourse of victimised Islam, as the militant both owns and
disowns responsibility for a calamity that the West and its cohorts have
brought upon themselves. The tapes allow the militant to become responsible “in
a prophetic and posthumous way, by broadcasting his impending death to ground
this responsibility, while simultaneously withdrawing from its ubiquity..
Indeed, the suicide bomber can only ground responsibility in this dual sense by
dying for it”. Devji sombrely reminds his readers that “this is the same thing
as saying that the only good Muslim is a dead Muslim”. This reflection could be
reinforced by the fact that Muslims form a large number of victims of jihadi
terror.
At times the author's theoretical ambition exceeds
itself, as in the conjecture that irrational cruelty could be an “epistemological”
pursuit of "the inhuman essence of enmity" or "man's common
humanity inside a foreign body". Inscrutable violence is an age-old human
experience - to depict it as an epistemological experiment is no more
enlightening than to remain silent. Were the experiments of Nazi doctors upon
concentration camp inmates any less epistemological? Addressing the concept of
humanity, Devji says that its use in medicine, humanitarianism and human rights
"transforms man into a kind of monster whose humanity is never quite
fulfilled...modern man's humanity remains abstract and dislocated...but in the
victim reduced to bare life humanity finally comes to light in minimal form, as
if violence itself were searching for man's essence". I think human rights
workers in Chhatisgarh or Chechnya, and doctors attending to the wounded in
Gaza have a clear picture of humanity that is not yet "purified of all
dross", nor reduced to Agamben's 'bare life'.
Devji sees a Gandhian spirit behind the militant's
rejection of his physical body leading to a posthumous recovery of his
humanity. He goes beyond "this militant critique of an aggregated
humanity" by suggesting that prosthetics and genetic engineering have made
it impossible "to locate the human essence even in bare life", since
“such lives can only be described as posthuman in their combination of
technical and biological parts...the all‑too real descendants of Frankenstein's
imaginary monster”. Wooden legs and gold teeth from bygone centuries come to
mind. Of greater import is the use of ‘posthuman’ as an ontological
description of militancy: “if the global Muslim community is seen by terrorists
to represent the suffering of humanity itself...the virtues of courage and
fearlessness can well be defined as the voice of humanity, though one deprived
of human subjectivity”. Having destroyed the body as a subject, and dismissed
life as the limit of humanity, suicide bombings "open up a space for the
posthuman". In his meditation on sacrifice as a form of sovereignty, Devji
compares bin Laden to Mahatma Gandhi, who also rejected a politics based on
fear and the management of life. “So both men value the kind of sacrifice that
literally volatilizes the body to make its humanity manifest in
fearlessness".
But "the body" is an abstraction, and
glosses over the crucial fact that Gandhi wanted the satyagrahi to sacrifice
his or her own body, whereas the terrorists are using their bodies to murder
people who do not want to die. Gandhi did not want to instil fear in others,
and insisted that “what is obtained by fear can be retained only as long as the
fear lasts”. This is where Devji's arguments cause me great unease. It is
almost as if the tidal wave of pain and grief caused to so many ordinary people
are mere ephemera, embarrassing details to be passed over by means of citations
from Gandhi where he preferred violence to cowardice, or spoke of thousands of
satyagrahis offering their lives to resist tyranny. Devji might well see the
militants as the standard‑bearers of an unborn form of sovereignty, but to
their surviving victims I suspect they appear as gatekeepers of the Abyss.
A provocative chapter named “Insulting the Prophet”
discusses popular mobilisations around hurt sentiment. Devji highlights the
contradictions of Western liberalism: “tolerance can have no moral content if
it exists only as the legal provision of mutual indifference”. He hails the
“positive, if particular” kind of tolerance that remains far more expansive
than “the negative universality of liberal tolerance”. He criticises the Muslim
liberals who have become the West’s preferred interlocutors for inter-faith
dialogue, and sees such interactions as a ploy for a monotheistic alliance that
occludes the fact that most Muslims live in proximity with polytheists.
Referring to the October 2007 letter to Christians by such liberals, he points
to the sponsored nature of such interventions, and the vast funds available for
the promotion of “moderate Islam”. This line of reasoning raises the question
of the immense financial support rendered by the USA, Saudi Arabia and Pakistan
for the anti-Soviet jihad of the 1980's. It also neglects the significance of
events such as the Jamiatul‑ulema‑e‑Hind’s mammoth rally against terrorism in
Delhi on May 31, 2008, at which a fatwa denouncing terrorism and signed by
leading clerics of the Darul Uloom was issued. The Deobandi ulema can by no
means be regarded as Western sponsored moderates.
There is a more disturbing line of thought. After
making compelling critiques of the controversies around the Danish cartoons of
2005 and the Pope’s Regenburg Address of 2006, Devji turns to the Catholic
campaign (marked in South Asia) against the screening of The Da Vinci Code,
a campaign that earned the support of Muslims. The film was banned in Pakistan
and certain Indian states “without, it seems, endangering freedom of speech
more generally”. Devji sees such demonstrations as examples of the “secular
vocabulary of hurt”, suggestive of the moral rather than juridical character of
community relations in South Asia. However, the re-cognition of sentiment in
secular law (as in provisions against hate speech, or Section 153A IPC), does
not indicate that the politics of hurt are as harmless as Devji suggests.
Vicious campaigns have been mobilised around the representation (and
fabrication) of hurt - foremost among them being the RSS-led movement for the
destruction of the Babri Masjid. In India, hurt sentiment is the preferred
pretext for the self-appointed commanders of identity to unleash mayhem
disguised as crimes of passion. The latest example of this is Raj Thackeray,
who fancies himself the defender of Marathi sentiment. I should mention that The
Da Vinci Code may be freely viewed on TV.
For Devji, the spectacle of suicide bombers dying
alongside their victims may be seen as "the dark side of humanity's global
brotherhood". He names this the "language of violence". For Al‑Qaeda,
“terror is the only form in which global freedom and equality are now
available". "Its true purpose is pedagogical, to school these
unbelievers in the forgotten language of ethics and principles". He
invokes Gandhi's separation of self‑sacrifice from killing, suggesting that
this separation is possible in militant Islam as well. (Gandhi and Osama are
the main characters in the book). Thus, "the victim is becoming more and
more a symbolic presence in the practice of militancy, one often dispensed with
altogether". Even if we agree with this interpretation of terror as a
perverse language (the image of the killer expiating for his deeds by his own
death goes back to an older tradition, notably to nineteenth-century Russia),
we simply cannot gloss over the philosophical chasm that separates Gandhi and
the violent men. At one point Devji argues that terrorist attacks against
infrastructure "bring about a Gandhian resolution to the problem posed by
an abstract humanity" - apropos Gandhi's critique of the railway - by
“participat(ing) in his enterprise of reducing an abstract humanity to a
multiplicity of concrete individuals”. The same result may be observed in
American or Israeli bombing attacks on infrastructure with their inevitable
"collateral damage". Would it not be absurd to see these as an
inadvertent accomplishment of a Gandhian enterprise?
It is difficult to agree that terrorism's victims are
becoming "a symbolic presence", if by that Devji wants to tell us
that killing people is incidental to its aims. Fresh corpses may indeed be
symbolic, but their appearance is central to the deed ‑ this is borne out by
Devji's own citations of speeches by bin Laden: "if it pains you too see
your victims..then remember our victims"; and al‑Zawahiri: "if they
taste some of what they are inflicting on our women and children, then they
will start giving up their arrogance". As Hannah Arendt observed, "the
practice of violence, like all action, changes the world, but the most probably
change is a more violent world". The 'language of violence' ‑ and I doubt
if Arendt (whom Devji often cites) would have thought the term valid at all ‑
is a semantic debacle that undermines the intended meaning of the act at the
very moment of ignition.
Sacrifice does not make suicide bombers disinterested
and selfless actors because of self-annihilation. Nor is proper to refer to
their deeds as “destroying interest itself in spectacular gestures...that unite
perpetrators and victims into a single humanity”. (Surely the dead qualify as
posthuman?). Sometimes self-destruction is the only available relief for
feelings of immense anger, humiliation and dis-empowerment. The difference
between jihadi bombers and self-immolating Buddhist monks in the Vietnam of the
1970's lies in the fact that the latter did not use their sacrifice to kill. An
involuntary sacrifice is not a sacrifice in the Gandhian sense.
Devji believes that the militants have revolutionised
Islam; and that “by operating in an arena without political leaders or
institutions of its own”, they provide a vision of the future. He asks why
“religion (has) come to provide the only vocabulary we have to describe this
new world”. The ancient question of virtuous murder haunts this book, as does
the unstated theodicean premise that terrorism will lead to some positive end.
Rationalist secularism is founded on the scientistic premise that metaphysical
questions such as the nature of sovereignty and humanity have either been
settled, or lie within a religious province. It is not surprising that
religious discourse appears to be the sole venue of transcendent speculation.
But is it therefore “the only vocabulary” available to us? I think not. And the
fascination with sacrificial death is not novel, nor peculiar to Islam, global
or otherwise. Here is Ernst Junger, witness to the bloodletting of two world
wars, in 1930: “With admiration, we watch how German youth, at the beginning of
this crusade of reason...raise the battle cry...glowing, enraptured, hungering
after death in a way unique in our history”. Lest we forget, in our time the
Tamil Tigers were the first to convert human beings into walking bombs. No,
these ghastly sacrifices have a hoary lineage, and I sincerely doubt they have
resolved any serious questions regarding modern notions of ‘humanity’.
A bibliography would have been useful. So would a more
carefully drafted index. Gandhi is cited (from a CUP version of Hind Swaraj)
as telling his imaginary interlocutor, "What we need to do is to kill
ourselves", whereas the Navajivan translation renders the sentence
"what we need to do is to sacrifice ourselves". The difference is
significant.
Devjis' book is challenging, and deserves to be read
widely. What it discloses most starkly is the optic schism in today's world.
Their cruelty renders the humanitarianism spoken of by Islamic militants a
non-language, and melds it seamlessly into cannibalistic modernity. But the
'surgical' air strikes of Western “humanitarian warfare” are no less oxymoronic
assaults upon meaningful speech. For the president of the USA to acknowledge
America may have made ‘mistakes’, and may “not be perfect”, is a tectonic shift
in the attitude of the US establishment, long addicted to Orwellian euphemism
as a handy opiate for a pliant media. Barack Hussein could say no more. After
George Bush and Co., our sighs of relief go to show how little we have come to
expect. But in the eyes of many non‑Westerners, America's double standard is
breathtaking. Speaking only of Iraq, after a million deaths and the enforced
migration of millions of refugees, after a war deceitfully launched and branded
illegal by the UN Secretary General, after blatant violations of international
law by the US and its closest West Asian ally, we learn that the defenders of
the Free World are a degree away from perfection. Blink. You can say that
again.