NB: These nuggets of wisdom have provided me much intellectual nourishment. I shall keep adding to them and hope that readers will enjoy them: DS
Bhagwadgita
Ahara-nidra-bhaya-maithunam ca // samanyam
etat pasubhir naranam
dharmo hi tesam adhiko viseso // dharmena hinah pasubhih samanah
Hunger, sleep, fear
and sex are common to men and animals
What distinguishes
men from animals is the knowledge of right and wrong
Bhagwadgita; Translated by Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan, 1948, 1971, p 79
Socrates: And what do you say of piety, Euthyphro?
Is not piety, according to your definition, loved by all the gods?
Euthyphro: Certainly.
Socrates: Because it is pious or holy, or for some
other reason?
Euthyphro: No, that is the reason.
Socrates: It is loved because it is holy, not holy
because it is loved?
Epicurus (341–270 BC)
Is God willing to prevent evil, but not able?
Then he is not omnipotent.
Is he able, but not willing?
Then he is malevolent.
Is he both able, and willing?
Then whence cometh evil?
Is he neither able nor willing?
Then why call him God?
G.W.F. Hegel: This is the hallmark of the sublime and absolute destiny of man - that
he knows what good and evil are, and that it is his will which chooses either
the one or the other. In short, he can be held responsible, for good as well as
for evil, and not just this or that particular circumstance and for everything
around him and within him, but also for the good and evil which are inherent in
his individual freedom. Only the animal can be described as totally
innocent.’ (Introduction to the lectures on the philosophy of world history, 1830
(CUP, 1975; p 90-91)
Zhuang Zhi: (370-287
BC) Everyone knows the usefulness of what is useful, but few know the
usefulness of what is useless
Christopher Colmo: Theoretical contemplation satisfies our eros
given the way we are built. Philosophy is good not because the truth is what it
is but because we are what we are. The truth is good because we love it.
(Consider Plato's Euthyphro, where we are asked whether the gods love what is
pious because it is pious, or alternatively, whether something is pious only
because the gods love it.) Reason and Revelation in the Thought of Leo Strauss; Interpretation, Fall 1990, Vol. 18, No. 1; p 155
Leo Strauss: It was (Heidegger’s) contempt for these permanencies (such as the
distinction between the noble and the base) that led the most radical
historicist in 1933 to submit to, or rather to welcome, as a dispensation of
fate, the verdict of the least wise and least moderate part of his nation while
it was in its least wise and least moderate mood, and at the same time to speak
of wisdom and moderation. The biggest event of 1933 would rather seem to have
proved, if such proof was necessary, that man cannot abandon the question of
the good society, and that he cannot free himself from the responsibility for
answering it by deferring to History or to any other power different from his
own reason.’ What is Political Philosophy,
(1959) p 27
Men are constantly
attracted and deluded by two opposite charms: the charm of competence which is
engendered by mathematics and everything akin to mathematics, and the charm of
humble awe, which is engendered by meditation on the human soul and its
experiences. Philosophy is characterized by the gentle, if firm, refusal to
succumb to either charm. (ibid, p 40)
Michael Sprinkler on Erich Heller: Modern philosophy frequently has made the fantastic
distinction between the life of the mind and life in the world, but always at a
frightful cost to itself and to the world. It is this entirely artificial
distinction that Erich Heller wishes to expose in all its falsity when he
reminds us, contrary to a certain tradition of apology among some of
Heidegger's American interpreters, that it was precisely in the name of
thinking and philosophy that Heidegger supported the accession to power of
Hitler and the Nazis: ...
it was not the private person Martin Heidegger but unmistakably
the author of Being and Time who accepted in 1933 the office of Rector of Freiburg University,
prematurely vacated by a scholar thought to be less fit to lead the academic
revolution, the Gleichschaltung, that the new rulers demanded. Unmistakably the
author of Being and Time, for again and again, in speeches, pronouncements, and
official letters he verbally behaved as if with the arrival of Hitler Being had
unexpectedly and triumphantly returned to Time, choosing as its vessel the German
nation in the manner of Jehovah's once electing the Jews... Michael Sprinkler, The Tragic Vision: Erich Heller
and the Critique of Modernism; Salmagundi, No.
52/53 (1981)
George Orwell on socialism: We have got to admit that if Fascism is
everywhere advancing, this is largely the fault of Socialists themselves.
Partly it is due to the mistaken Communist tactic of sabotaging democracy, i.e.
sawing off the branch you are sitting on; but still more to the fact that
Socialists have, so to speak, presented their case wrong side foremost. They
have never made it sufficiently clear that the essential aims of Socialism are
justice and liberty. With their eyes glued to economic facts, they have
proceeded on the assumption that man has no soul, and explicitly or implicitly
they have set up the goal of a materialistic Utopia. As a result Fascism has
been able to play upon every instinct that revolts against hedonism and a cheap
conception of ‘progress’. From The Road to Wigan Pier, (1937) ch 12
Hannah Arendt on Heidegger: In his political behavior, in any
case, Heidegger has provided us with more than ample warning that we should
take him seriously. [As is well known, he entered the Nazi Party in a very
sensational way in 1933-an act which made him stand out pretty much by himself
among colleagues of the same calibre. Further, in his capacity as rector of
Freiburg University, he forbade Husserl, his teacher and friend, whose
lecture chair he had inherited, to enter the faculty, because Husserl was a
jew. Finally, it has been rumored that he has placed himself at the disposal of
the French occupational authorities for the re-education of the German people.]
In view of the truly comic aspect of
this development and in view of the no less genuinely abysmal state of
political thought in German universities, one is tempted simply to dismiss the
whole business. What speaks against such a dismissal is, among other things,
that this entire mode of behavior has such exact parallels in German Romanticism
that one can hardly believe them to result from the sheer coincidence of a purely personal failure of
character. Heidegger is really (let us hope) the last Romantic - an immensely
talented Friedrich Schlegel or Adam Muller, as it were, whose complete lack of
responsibility is attributable to a spiritual playfulness that stems in part from delusions of genius and in
part from despair. (What is Existential Philosophy? (1946) in Essays in Understanding (1994); p 187
Leo Strauss: A social science that
cannot speak of tyranny with the same confidence with which medicine speaks,
for example, of cancer, cannot understand social phenomena as what they are. It
is therefore not scientific. Present day social science finds itself in this
condition. Restatement on Xenophon's Hiero, in On Tyranny, (1948, 2000, p 177)
Philosophy as such
is nothing but genuine awareness of the problems, i.e., of the fundamental and
comprehensive problems. It is impossible to think about these problems without
becoming inclined toward a solution, toward one or the other of the very few
typical solutions. Yet as long as there is no wisdom but only quest for wisdom,
the evidence of all solutions is necessarily smaller than the evidence of the
problems. Therefore the philosopher ceases to be a philosopher at the moment at
which the “subjective certainty” of a solution becomes stronger than his awareness
of the problematic character of that solution. At that moment the sectarian is
born. The danger of succumbing to the attraction of solutions is essential to
philosophy which, without incurring this danger, would degenerate into playing
with the problems. But the philosopher does not necessarily succumb to this
danger, as is shown by Socrates, who never belonged to a sect and never founded
one… (ibid, p 196)
Hannah Arendt to
Mary McCarthy: The chief fallacy is to believe that
Truth is a result which comes at the end of a thought process. Truth, on the
contrary, is always the beginning of thought.. Thinking starts after an
experience of Truth has struck home, so to speak. The difference between
philosophers and other people is that the former refuse to let go, but not that
they are the only receptacles of Truth.. Truth, in other words, is not in thought,
but... it is the condition for the possibility of thinking. It is both
beginning and a priori.” Carol Brightman, ed., Between Friends: The Correspondence of
Hannah Arendt and Mary McCarthy 1949-1975
C.S.
Lewis: The
whole point of seeing through something is to see something through it. It is
good that the window should be transparent, because the street or garden beyond
it is opaque. How (would it be) if you saw through the garden too. It is no use
trying 'to see through' first principles. If you see through everything, then
everything is transparent. But a wholly transparent world is an invisible
world. To see through all things is the same as not to see. Abolition of Man, (1943) p 40
Stanley Rosen: If there is no human nature that remains
constant within historical change, and so defines the perspectives of
individual readers as perspectives
upon a common humanity, then reading is impossible.... If the contingent is intelligible, that is, if it is amenable to judgement, then the basis of intelligibility or judgement cannot itself be contingent. It is true that the wise decision under present circumstances may be foolish under other circumstances, but the wisdom of the decision under present circumstances is not arbitrary. To judge is to understand, not to create ex nihilo... Hermeneutics as Politics (1987), p 146, 149
Every account that we give of the “meaning” of a Platonic text is
incomplete, and corresponds to some perspective or another. This is not because
the truth is perspectival or radically historical, but because it always
exhibits itself in a determinate manner. I agree with Strauss that we can find
the truth within a given determination. But there is no end to the number of
determinate appearances of truth. Differently stated, there are truths, not the truth... Essays in Philosophy (Ancient) (2013) p. 57
If
there is a fusion of horizons it depends upon something independent of the
fusion itself, namely, upon some understanding of the nature of the work we are
attempting to appropriate. And this condition carries with it the requirement
that works of art have some nature or being that is independent of how we
appropriate them. There must be something to appropriate or there will be no
interpretations.... Interpretation
is the act of restating a commonly accessible truth which we have antecedently
understood in a local representation of our own. The restatement of truth does
not transform its universality but allows it to function within a modified
context. Interpretation, or the transfer of universality from one local
representation to another, is the process by which we arrive at an
understanding of the universal significance of locality in human
life. Without this understanding, the local is meaningless, and history is
reduced to rubbish.” (Metaphysics in Ordinary Language, (1999), p 201
Bernard Yack: But Fustel
de Coulanges’s efforts have no more broken the spell of Rousseau's rhetoric
than Volney's. Demonstrations of historical inaccuracy, however well
documented, rarely have much effect on the longing to escape modern limitations
that the Rousseauian perspective on classical antiquity inspires. Critics like
Volney and Fustel de Coulanges assume that a false reconstruction of the past
sours the Rousseauian's appreciation of the present, when it is more often the
case that it is an analysis of the present that produces the need to distort
the past The Longing for Total
Revolution; p 79
Yakub ibn Ishaq
al-Kindi (died ca 870 AD): We
should not be ashamed to acknowledge truth and to assimilate it from whatever
source it comes to us, even if it is brought to us by former generations and
foreign peoples. For him who seeks the truth there is nothing of higher value
than truth itself; it never cheapens or debases him who reaches for it but
ennobles and honours him. (cited
in Karen Armstrong, History of God, p. 172
Johann Wolfgang Goethe (1749-1832): How could I write songs of hatred when I
felt no hate? And, between ourselves, I never hated the French, although I
thanked God when we were rid of them. How could I, to whom the only significant
things are civilization and barbarism, hate a nation which is among the most
cultivated in the world, and to which I owe a great part of my own culture? In
any case this business of hatred between nations is a curious thing. You will
always find it more powerful and barbarous on the lowest levels of
civilization. But there exists a level at which it wholly disappears, and where
one stands, so to speak, above the nations, and feels the weal or woe of a neighbouring
people as though it were one's own’: Will Durant (1967); The
Story of Civilization Volume 10: Rousseau and Revolution; Ch 24; p 607
Christopher Colmo: Philosophy does not refute religion by
attempting to achieve a secular wisdom. Rather philosophy is the sympathetic
but incorruptible judge of the failure of all attempts at wisdom, sacred or
profane: Reason and Revelation in the Thought of Leo
Strauss (1990)
Mark Lilla: An ideology gives people the illusion of understanding more than they do:
Afterword to The Reckless Mind
Leo Strauss: If nihilism is the rejection of the principles of civilisation as
such, and if civilisation is based on recognition of the fact that the subject
of civilisation is man as man, every interpretation of science and morals in
terms of races, or of nations, or of cultures, is strictly speaking nihilistic.
Whoever accepts the idea of a Nordic or German or Faustic science, e.g.,
rejects eo ipso the idea of science.
Different ‘cultures’ may have produced different types of ‘science’; but only
one of them can be true, can be science. The nihilist implication of the
nationalist interpretation of science in particular can be described somewhat
differently in the following terms. Civilisation is inseparable from learning,
from the desire to learn from anyone who can teach us something worthwhile. The
nationalist interpretation of science or philosophy implies that we cannot
really learn anything worthwhile from people who do not belong to our nation or
our culture. The few Greeks whom we usually have in mind when we speak of the
Greeks, were distinguished from the barbarians, so to speak exclusively by
their willingness to learn even from barbarians; whereas the barbarian, the
non-Greek barbarian as well as the Greek barbarian, believes that all his
questions are solved by, or on the basis of, his ancestral tradition. German
Nihilism 1941
Max Weber: What is the meaning of science as a vocation,
now after all these former illusions, the ‘way to true being,’ the ‘way to true
art,’ the ‘way to true nature,’ the ‘way to true God,’ the ‘way to true
happiness,’ have been dispelled? Tolstoi has given the simplest answer, with
the words: ‘Science is meaningless
because it gives no answer, the only question important for us: “what shall we
do and how shall we live?” That science does not give an answer to this is
indisputable. The only question that remains is the sense in which science
gives ‘no’ answer, and whether or not science might yet be of some use to the
one who puts the question correctly. (Science as a Vocation, speech at Munich
University, 1917)
Simone Weil on violence: The man who is the possessor of force seems to walk through a non-resistant element; in the human substance that surrounds him nothing has the power to interpose, between the impulse and the act, the tiny interval that is reflection: The Iliad, or the Poem of Force; 1940
Mary Catherine Bateson: The
timing of death, like the ending of a story, gives a changed meaning to what
preceded it: With a Daughter's Eye: A Memoir of Margaret Mead and Gregory Bateson (1984)
Stanley Rosen: The crux of the matter is not one's attitude
toward science and technology, and certainly not whether one is a “liberal” or “conservative”
in the debased and largely mindless sense in which these terms are used
today. Instead, it is our conception
of reason, and specifically of the connection between reason and the good. Those who define the good
as the powerful, whether they be positivists or existentialists, at once deprive
themselves of the capacity to distinguish between good and evil, and so they
cannot speak rationally of the goodness of reason. Nihilism: A
Philosophical Essay, 1969, p. 110
Is there available
in our ordinary experience an icon of what Socrates means by the ‘vision’ or ‘prophecy’
of the good? I believe that there is - the good man. A good man, as we observe
him within our daily lives, is not ‘useful for…’ in the same sense that tools,
food, acts, even just and beautiful things exhibit utility. Entirely apart from
the happiness which may justly accrue to the good man because of his
consciousness that he is good, there is a certain fulfillment, completion or
perfection which shines forth from such a man, and which we too admire, even
perhaps without envy or desire, because of its splendor.. (ibid) p 172
Alexandre Koyre neither the
totalitarian states nor their parties are secret societies in the precise sense
of the term... they operate in public and make a· great play for publicity.
Which amounts to just this: they conspire in broad daylight. The Political Function of the Modern Lie (1945)
Leszek Kolakowski: The devil decided to go back to
the old notion of politics based on truth - as opposed to contract or consensus.
He invented ideological states, that is to say, states whose legitimacy is
grounded in the fact that their owners are owners of truth. If you oppose such
a state or its system, you are an enemy of truth. The father of the lie
employed the idea of truth as his powerful weapon. Truth by definition is
universal, not tied to any particular nation or state. A nation or a state is
not just a nation or a state, trying to assert its particular interest, to
defend itself, to expand, to conquer new territories, to build an empire and so
on. It is a carrier of universal truth, as in the old days of the crusades. ... The devil, as the
medieval theologians used to say, is simia
dei, an ape of God. By inventing the ideological states he produced a
caricatural imitation of theocracy. In fact the new order was to be much more
thorough and complete than any Christian state of old, as it dispensed with any
distinction between secular and religious authorities, concentrating instead
both spiritual and physical power in one place; and the devil gave it not only
all the instruments of coercion and education but the entire wealth of the
nation as well, including the nation itself. Theocracy, or rather aleteiocracy,
the rule of truth, had, at a certain moment, achieved an almost perfect form. [Chapter 15: Politics and the Devil From Modernity on Endless Trial; pp 189]
What philosophy is about is not Truth… The cultural role of philosophy is not to deliver truth but to build the spirit of truth, and this means never to let the inquisitive energy of mind go to sleep, never to stop questioning what appears to be obvious and definitive, always to defy the seemingly intact resources of common sense, always to suspect that there might be "another side" in what we take for granted, and never to allow us to forget that there are questions that lie beyond the legitimate horizon of science and are nonetheless crucially important to the survival of humanity.. All
the most traditional worries of philosophers - how to tell good from evil, true from
false, real from unreal, being from nothingness, just from unjust... man from animal, mind from body... - all of them boil down to the quest for meaning; and they presuppose that in dissecting
such questions we may employ the instruments of reason, even if the ultimate outcome
is the dismissal of reason... Philosophers neither sow nor harvest,
they only move the soil. They do not discover truth; but they are needed to keep
the energy of mind alive... (ibid, p 135)
Stanley Rosen: When philosophy is
transformed into nationalism, wisdom itself becomes an ideology, and instead of
a homogenous world state, we arrive at a perpetual state of global war: (Essays
in Modern Philosophy, 2013, p 112)
... it is hard
to see how Heidegger, despite his distinction between Geschichte and Historie, (history as lived vs history as an
object of inquiry) makes it possible for man to take a responsible stand toward history. One must
seriously question the adequacy of the resolute acceptance of tradition - i.e.,
what happens - as a criterion for human conduct. An ontology which cannot
assist man in his struggle to preserve himself from his own actions runs the
risk of Nihilism, which I regard as the consequence of the claustrophobia of
complete immanentism masquerading as freedom. (The Quarrel Between Poetry and Philosophy, p 147)
Wherever philosophy renounces the authority of reason to choose ends or
values in a way not vitiated by passion or history, by the urgency of the flesh
or the transience of taste, a vacuum is created in our lives that must necessarily
be filled by unreasonable, and indeed by insane or absurd, ideologies. In sum,
if it is true that ours is an age of nihilism, the cause lies in the fact that
what we regard as progress in our understanding of "how to be reasonable'
' is actually retrogression or decay…. I am not suggesting that reason has
nothing to do with counting and inferring, or that it is entirely independent
of history. The problem is to do justice to the richness and complexity of
man's rational nature, to avoid a denatured conception of reason…
When courage and justice are sundered from wisdom and moderation, they
cannot serve as the basis for a rational political philosophy, but give birth
to ideology instead...The severance of the heart from the head, whether
directed by the head or the heart, leads neither to integrity nor resolve, but
only to a meaningless death. Philosophy and Ideology: Reflections
on Heidegger; Social Research, Vol. 35, No. 2 (1968), p. 261-2;
285
Vassily Grossman (1905-1964): Whenever we see the dawn of an eternal good... whenever we see this dawn, the blood of children and old people is always shed... Human history is not the battle of good struggling to overcome evil. It is a battle fought by a great evil struggling to crush a small kernel of human kindness. But if what is human in human beings has not been destroyed even now, then evil will never conquer: Life and Fate, (1960) 2011, pp 390-394
A. J. P. Taylor: In the state of nature which Hobbes
imagined, violence was the only law, and life was 'nasty, brutish and short'.
Though individuals never lived in this state of nature, the Great Powers of
Europe have always done so." (The Struggle for Mastery in
Europe 1848-1918)
Hannah Arendt: totalitarian solutions may well survive the
fall of totalitarian regimes in the form of strong temptations which will come
up whenever it seems impossible to alleviate political, social, or economic
misery in a manner worthy of man… It may even be that the true predicaments of
our time will assume their authentic form – though not necessarily the cruelest
– only when totalitarianism has become a thing of the past. The Origins
of Totalitarianism (1948) p 592-593
The
totalitarian element in Marxism is as little the concept of class or classless
society as the concept of race or race society, as such, is what made Nazism
totalitarian. In both instances, the decisive element is
the belief that history can be made, which teaches certain procedures by which
one can bring about its end-and of course never does. The breaking of eggs in
action never leads to anything more interesting than the breaking of eggs. The
result is identical with the activity itself: it is a breaking, not an omelet.. Arendt, The ex communists;
in Essays in Understanding,
1930-1954; New
York; (1954), 1994, p 396-7
Leo Strauss on Machiavelli: The recovery of
ancient virtue consists of the re-imposition of the terror and fear that had
made men good at the beginning. Machiavelli thus explains what his concern with
the recovery of ancient modes and orders means fundamentally: men were good at
the beginning, not because of innocence but because they were gripped by terror
and fear-by the initial and radical terror and fear; at the beginning there is not Love but Terror; Machiavelli's wholly new teaching is based on this
alleged insight (which anticipates Hobbes' doctrine of the state of nature). Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey; (eds) History of Political Philosophy (1987); (1963); 1972; p 310. NB: Gandhi
represented love; communalism represented terror. The foundation of India and
Pakistan was the unstable mixture of the two: DS
Bruno Latour on
Michel Serres: The mob in a state of
crisis cannot agree on anything but on a victim, a scapegoat, a sacrifice.
Beneath any boundary is buried a sacrificial victim.. (Serres) slowly realized
that the sciences were not a way to limit violence but to fuel it. He decided
to hear and to feel this terrible earth shaking tremor travelling from
Hiroshima, the only date in history that he takes as a real turning-point; the
earth has been shaking ever since…. Thanatocraty - Serres’ word for the black
triad made by scientists, politicians and industrialists: The
Enlightenment without the Critique: A Word on Michel Serres' Philosophy (pub. 1987)
Iris Murdoch: Freedom, we find out, is not an
inconsequential chucking of one’s weight about, it is the disciplined
overcoming of self. Humility is not a peculiar habit of self-effacement, rather
like having an inaudible voice, it is self-less respect for reality and one of
the most difficult and central of all virtues... Existentialism, in both its Continental and
its Anglo-Saxon versions, is an attempt to solve the problem without really
facing it: to solve it by attributing to the individual an empty, lonely
freedom, a freedom, if he wishes, to 'fly in the face of the facts'. What it
pictures is indeed the fearful solitude of the individual marooned upon a tiny
island in the middle of a sea of scientific facts, and morality escaping from
science only by a wild leap of the will. But our situation is not like
this..
Leszek Kolakowski: To reject the sacred
is to reject our own limits. It is also to reject the idea of evil, for the
sacred reveals itself through sin, imperfection, and evil; and evil, in turn,
can be identified only through the sacred. To say that evil is contingent is to
say that there is no evil, and therefore that we have no need of a sense that
is already there, fixed and imposed on us whether we will it or not…If it is
true that in order to make society more tolerable, we must believe that it can
be improved, it is also true that there must always be people who think of the
price paid for every step of what we call progress. The order of the sacred is
also a sensitivity to evil.. , The revenge of the sacred in secular culture in Modernity on Endless trial..
p 73
Niels Bohr: “The fact
that religions through the ages have spoken in images, parables, and paradoxes
means simply that there are no other ways of grasping the reality to which they
refer. But that does not mean that it is not a genuine reality. And splitting
this reality into an objective and a subjective side won’t get us very far.” Niels
Bohr on Subjective vs. Objective Reality
Karl Marx: Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopaedic compendium, its
logic in popular form, its spiritual point d’honneur, its
enthusiasm, its moral sanction, its solemn complement, and its universal basis
of consolation and justification. It is the fantastic realization of
the human essence since the human essence has not acquired any
true reality. The struggle against religion is, therefore, indirectly the
struggle against that world whose spiritual aroma is
religion.
Religious suffering is, at one and the same time,
the expression of real suffering and a protest against
real suffering. Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a
heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions. It is the opium of
the people.The
abolition of religion as the illusory happiness of the people
is the demand for their real happiness. To call on them to
give up their illusions about their condition is to call on them to give
up a condition that requires illusions. The criticism of religion is,
therefore, in embryo, the criticism of that vale of tears of
which religion is the halo: Karl Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (1843)
Russell Jacoby: The arrogance of those who come later preens itself with the
notion that the past is dead and gone. Few can resist introducing stock
criticism of Freud - be it of the left or right -without the standard observation
that Freud was a nineteenth-century Viennese. The endless repetition of such
statements suggests the decline of critical thinking; the modem mind can no
longer think thought, only can locate it in time and space. The activity of
thinking decays to the passivity of classifying. Freud is explained away by
positioning him in a nineteenth-century Vienna. Today, bred and fed on
twentieth-century urbane and liberal
feed, we have apparently left behind history itself and can view the past with
the pleasure of knowing that we are no longer part of it. Yet little bears the
imprint of the present historical period more than this fake historical
consciousness: the argument that past thought is past because it is past is a
transparent alibi for the present. To accuse such reasoning with its own logic,
it is the contemporary form of relativism; debased sociology of knowledge seeks
to avoid thought by mechanically matching it with specific social strata and
historical eras. Its awareness of historical transformation ideologically stops
short of itself; its own viewpoint is considered neutral and absolute truth,
outside - not inside - history.. Social Amnesia, (1975); Chapter 1, Social Amnesia and the new Ideologues
Waller R. Newell: Contrary to Heidegger’s
absorption of all political motivations into “technology,” the Nazis did not
carry out the Holocaust because they had developed the technology - they
developed the technology because they wanted to carry out the Holocaust. One has
to think through why... At bottom, it is hard
to imagine a more fundamental lack of moderation than Heidegger’s equation - shared
by Kojève - of democracy and totalitarianism on the grounds that the
technological dynamo of modernization has swallowed up all such distinctions between
better and worse regimes and rendered them naive.. Kojève’s Hegel,
Hegel’s Hegel, and Strauss’s Hegel; in Timothy Burns & Bryan-Paul Frost; Philosophy, History, and Tyranny; 2016: pp 244-249
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri: Many of the concepts
dear to postmodernists and post-colonialists find a perfect correspondence in
the current ideology of corporate capital and the world market. The ideology of
the world market has always been the anti-foundational and anti-essentialist
discourse par excellence. Circulation, mobility, diversity, and mixture are its
very conditions of possibility... Differences (of commodities, populations, cultures, and so forth)
seem to multiply infinitely in the world market, which attacks nothing more
violently than fixed boundaries: it overwhelms any binary division with its
infinite multiplicities: Hardt and Negri Empire, p 150 (2000) (One of postmodernism’s
most subtle manoeuvres has been to present such tendencies as liberating and
progressive - comment on the above citation, by David Hawkes, Ideology, p 11)
Bulle
Shah (1680-1757):
pad pad oh hazaar kitaabaan / kadi apne aap nu
padheya nahi
ja ja varde mandir maseeti / kade mann apne
vich vadeyaa nahi
avein lardaa hai, shaitaan de naal bandeya / kadi
nafz apne naal ladeya nahi
Aakhe peer Bulleh Shah aasmani pharna aeN / jehra
man wich wasda unhoN pharya nahin