Susan Neiman - Evil in Modern Thought // Lecture: 'Hannah Arendt's Disruptive Truth Telling'
This is the Preface to Susan Neiman's acclaimed study in moral philosophy, Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy (2002). Links to reviews are available at the bottom of the page
The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and familiarity. (One is unable to notice something - because it is always before one's eyes.) The real foundations of his inquiry do not strike a person at all. And this means: we fail to be struck by what, once seen, is most striking and most powerful.
The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and familiarity. (One is unable to notice something - because it is always before one's eyes.) The real foundations of his inquiry do not strike a person at all. And this means: we fail to be struck by what, once seen, is most striking and most powerful.
Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, #129
'Every time we make the judgment this ought not to have happened, we are stepping onto a path that leads straight to the problem of evil. Note that it is as little a moral problem, strictly speaking, as it is a theological one. One can call it the point at which ethics and metaphysics, epistemology and aesthetics meet, collide, and throw up their hands. At issue are questions about what the structure of the world must be like for us to think and act within it. Those questions will quickly become historical. For what most demands explanation is not how moral judgments are justified, but why those that are so clearly justified were disregarded in the past. When one begins to seek explanation, one can end in anything from myth, like the Fall, to metaphysics, like Hegel's Phenomenology. What's important is that the place one begins is perfectly ordinary... I believe it is the place where philosophy begins, and threatens to stop. For it involves questions more natural, urgent, and pervasive than the sceptical epistemological quandaries conventionally said to drive modern philosophy..'
The eighteenth century used the word Lisbon
much as we use the word Auschwitz today. How much weight
can a brute reference carry? It takes no more than the name of a place to mean:
the collapse of the most basic trust in the world, the grounds that make
civilization possible. Learning this, modern readers may feel wistful: lucky
the age to which an earthquake can do so much damage. The 1755 earthquake that
destroyed the city of Lisbon , and
several thousand of its inhabitants, shook the Enlightenment all the way to East
Prussia , where an unknown minor scholar named
Immanuel Kant wrote three essays on the nature of earthquakes for the
Konigsberg newspaper. He was not alone. The reaction to the earthquake was as
broad as it was swift. Voltaire and Rousseau found another occasion to quarrel
over it, academies across Europe devoted prize essay
contests to it, and the six-year-old Goethe, according to several sources, was
brought to doubt and consciousness for the first time. The earthquake affected
the best minds in Europe , but it wasn't confined to
them. Popular reactions ranged from sermons to eyewitness sketches to very bad
poetry. Their number was so great as to cause sighs in the contemporary press
and sardonic remarks from Frederick
the Great, who thought the cancellation of carnival preparations months after
the disaster to be overdone.
It cannot be the case that philosophers failed to notice an
event of this magnitude. On the contrary, one reason given for the absence of
philosophical reflection is the magnitude of the task. What occurred in Nazi
death camps was so absolutely evil that, like no other event in human history,
it defies human capacities for understanding. But the question of the
uniqueness and magnitude of Auschwitz is itself a
philosophical one; thinking about it could take us to Kant and Hegel,
Dostoevsky and Job. One need not settle questions about the relationship of Auschwitz
to other crimes and suffering to take it as paradigmatic of the sort of evil
that contemporary philosophy rarely examines. The differences in intellectual
responses to the earthquake at Lisbon
and the mass murder at Auschwitz are differences not
only in the nature of the events but also in our intellectual constellations.
What counts as a philosophical problem and what counts as a philosophical
reaction, what is urgent and what is academic, what is a matter of memory and
what is a matter of meaning - all these are open to change.
This book traces changes that have occurred in our
understanding of the self and its place in the world from the early
Enlightenment to the late twentieth century. Taking intellectual reactions to Lisbon
and Auschwitz as central poles of inquiry is a way of
locating the beginning and end of the modern. Focusing on points of doubt and
crisis allows us to examine our guiding assumptions by examining what
challenges them at points where they break down: what threatens our sense of
the sense of the world? That focus also underlies one of this book's central
claims: the problem of evil is the guiding force of modern thought. Most
contemporary versions of the history of philosophy will view this claim to be
less false than incomprehensible. For the problem of evil is thought to be a
theological one. Classically, it's formulated as the question: How could a good
God create a world full of innocent suffering?
Such questions have been
off-limits to philosophy since Immanuel Kant argued that God, along with many
other subjects of classical metaphysics, exceeded the limits of human
knowledge. If one thing might seem to unite philosophers on both sides of the Atlantic ,
it's the conviction that Kant's work proscribes not just future philosophical
references to God but most other sorts of foundation as well. From this
perspective, comparing Lisbon to Auschwitz
is merely mistaken. The mistake seems to lie in accepting the eighteenth
century's use of the word evil to refer to both acts of human cruelty and
instances of human suffering. That mistake might come naturally to a group of
theists, who were willing to give God the responsibility for both, but it
shouldn't confuse the rest of us. On this view Lisbon
and Auschwitz are two completely different kinds of
events. Lisbon denotes the sort of
thing insurance companies call natural disasters, to remove them from the
sphere of human action.
Thus human beings are absolved of responsibility not only
for causing or compensating them but even for thinking about them, except in
pragmatic and technological terms. Earthquakes and volcanoes, famines and
floods inhabit the borders of human meaning. We want to understand just so much
about them as might help us gain control. Only traditional - that is, premodern
- theists will seek in them significance. Auschwitz , by
contrast, stands for all that is meant when we use the word evil today:
absolute wrongdoing that leaves no room for account or expiation.
Initially, then, no two events will strike us as more
different. If there's a problem of evil engendered by Lisbon ,
it can occur only for the orthodox: how can God allow a natural order that
causes innocent suffering? The problem of evil posed by Auschwitz
looks like another entirely: how can human beings behave in ways that so
thoroughly violate both reasonable and rational norms? It is just this sense
that the problems are utterly different which marks modern consciousness. The
sharp distinction between natural and moral evil that now seems self-evident was
born around the Lisbon earthquake
and nourished by Rousseau. Tracing the history of that distinction, and the
ways in which the problems refused to stay separate, is one aim of this book.
A central reason for locating the modern as beginning at Lisbon
is precisely for its attempt to divide responsibility clearly. Close look at
that attempt will reveal all its irony. Though the philosophes perpetually
accused Rousseau of nostalgia, Voltaire's discussion of the earthquake left far
more in God's hands than did Rousseau's. And when Rousseau invented the modern
sciences of history and psychology to cope with questions the earthquake
brought to the surface, it was in defense of God's order. Ironies
notwithstanding, the consciousness that emerged after Lisbon
was an attempt at maturity. If Enlightenment is the courage to think for
oneself, it's also the courage to assume responsibility for the world into
which one is thrown. Radically separating what earlier ages called natural from
moral evils was thus part of the meaning of modernity. If Auschwitz
can be said to mark its ending, it is for the way it marks our terror. Modern
conceptions of evil were developed in the attempt to stop blaming God for the
state of the world, and to take responsibility for it on our own. The more
responsibility for evil was left to the human, the less worthy the species
seemed to take it on. We are left without direction. Returning to intellectual
tutelage isn't an option for many, but hopes for growing up now seem void.
The history of philosophy, like that of nations or
individuals, should teach us not to take for granted the intersection of
assumptions where we find ourselves standing at particular moments in time.
Learning this is a crucial part of the self-knowledge that was always
philosophy's goal. But history of philosophy achieves such knowledge only when
it is sufficiently historical. More often, the history of philosophy is
approached as if our constellations and categories were self-evident. In
broadest terms, we probably agree with Comte's view of intellectual history as
progressing from theological to metaphysical to scientific ages. On such a
view, thinkers whose world was shattered by the Lisbon
earthquake would confirm all conviction in Enlightenment naiveté. At best,
their reaction seems quaint, a sign of intellectual immaturity befitting an era
that found itself on the border between theology an metaphysics. If one
believes the world is ruled by a good an powerful father figure, it's natural
to expect his order to be comprehensibly just. Jettison that belief, and
whatever expectations remain are unresolved residues of childish fantasy. Thus
the intellectual shock waves generated by Lisbon ,
when noticed at all, are seen as the birth pangs of a sadder but wiser era that
has learned to live on its own.
This view, I will argue, is itself a historical one, for
nothing is easier than stating the problem of evil in nontheist terms. One can
state it, for example, as an argument with Hegel: not only is the real not
identical with the rational; they aren't even related. To make this
observation, you need no theory. Any observation of the world that continues
for more than a couple of minutes should do. Every time we make the judgment
this ought not to have happened, we are stepping onto a path that leads
straight to the problem of evil. Note that it is as little a moral problem, strictly
speaking, as it is a theological one. One can call it the point at which ethics
and metaphysics, epistemology and aesthetics meet, collide, and throw up their
hands. At issue are questions about what the structure of the world must be
like for us to think and act within it. Those questions will quickly become
historical. For what most demands explanation is not how moral judgments are
justified, but why those that are so clearly justified were disregarded in the
past. When one begins to seek explanation, one can end in anything from myth,
like the Fall, to metaphysics, like Hegel's Phenomenology. WhatÕs important is
that the place one begins is perfectly ordinary.
I believe it is the place where philosophy begins, and
threatens to stop. For it involves questions more natural, urgent, and
pervasive than the sceptical epistemological quandaries conventionally said to
drive modern philosophy. ..
Reviews:
Wall
Street Journal, 3 September 2002
NYTimes, 5 October 2002
NYTimes, 6 October 2002
Times Literary Supplement, 18 October 2002
Milliyet, 24 October 2002
NRC Handelsblad, 8 November 2002
Die Welt, 14 December 2002
Washington Post, 15 December 2002
First Things, January 2003
Forward, 28 March 2003
Culture Wars, 02/2003
Common Knowledge, Spring 2003
Filosofie Magazine, April 2003
Christian Century, April 5, 2003
CHOICE, June 2003
Weekly Standard, 9 June 2003
New York Review of Books, 12 June 2003
Galileu, Número 149, Decembro 2003
Harper's Magazine, January 2004
literaturkritik.de, Nr.7, Juli 2004
Freitag 34, 13.August 2004
The Globe and Mail, 11. September 2004
NYTimes, 5 October 2002
NYTimes, 6 October 2002
Times Literary Supplement, 18 October 2002
Milliyet, 24 October 2002
NRC Handelsblad, 8 November 2002
Die Welt, 14 December 2002
Washington Post, 15 December 2002
First Things, January 2003
Forward, 28 March 2003
Culture Wars, 02/2003
Common Knowledge, Spring 2003
Filosofie Magazine, April 2003
Christian Century, April 5, 2003
CHOICE, June 2003
Weekly Standard, 9 June 2003
New York Review of Books, 12 June 2003
Galileu, Número 149, Decembro 2003
Harper's Magazine, January 2004
literaturkritik.de, Nr.7, Juli 2004
Freitag 34, 13.August 2004
The Globe and Mail, 11. September 2004
+++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++
Susan Neiman: Hannah Arendt's Disruptive Truth Telling (Keynote address at the 50th anniversary conference): http://www.youtube.com/watch? v=VBhhkAcmrlg
Read the transcript 'Hannah Arendt's Disruptive Truth Telling'
50 Years On, A Seminal Work Is Alive and Debated
Fifty years after its publication, Hannah Arendt's Eichmann In Jerusalem is as relevant and controversial as ever. During a standing room only event, a distinguished panel and members of the audience debated its journalistic and philosophical merits at the Columbia Journalism School. Includes full video
50 Years On, A Seminal Work Is Alive and Debated
Fifty years after its publication, Hannah Arendt's Eichmann In Jerusalem is as relevant and controversial as ever. During a standing room only event, a distinguished panel and members of the audience debated its journalistic and philosophical merits at the Columbia Journalism School. Includes full video
In the trial, Eichmann presented himself merely as a civil servant for the Third Reich, following orders to deport millions to concentration camps at the behest of the Nazi leadership. He presented himself as a moral individual operating under the Kantian categorical imperative (whereas the moral law coincided with the law of his state, therefore, Hitler was the legislator of his morality). He professed no ideological or psychological allegiance to the ideas of Hitler. Nonetheless, in the end, he was sentenced to death. But Arendt observed in Eichmann a somewhat pathetic figure, unintelligent and weak-willed, and drew from this her concept of the "banality of evil", in which ordinary individuals can commit great acts of evil in the name of doing their duty or following the law.
The book was controversial for what seemed to be an almost sympathetic portrayal of a reviled figure, and later research and documents, such as Bettina Stangneth's Eichmann Before Jerusalem have revealed that Eichmann was fully in support of the genocide he enacted. Some critics would argue that this evidence invalidates Arendt's entire thesis, but in many texts and lectures, especially those at this conference, maintain that Arendt's ideas remain as pertinent as ever. Arendt questioned how intention functioned under totalitarian violence, and criticized its disappearance under such conditions. Moral choice remained an imperative, moreover, a universal imperative, unlike Eichamann's misinterpretation of Kant, which implied the subject in an international plurality. In writing about Eichmann, Arendt observed the larger historical world's disappearance into non-thinking and banality, and suggested new modes of moral philosophy as they related to international law. Even more deeply, it brings into question the role of thought in these "banal" procedures...
Also see:
Closing the Circle: article on Revolution in Frontier
Upinder Singh: On the Politics of War and Violence in Early Medieval India
Upinder Singh: On the Politics of War and Violence in Early Medieval India
"It's all business. One murder makes a villain. Millions, a hero. Numbers sanctify. Von Clausewitz said that war is the logical extension of diplomacy; Monsieur Verdoux feels that murder is the logical extension of business."